MARC보기
LDR00000nam u2200205 4500
001000000434272
00520200226143600
008200131s2019 ||||||||||||||||| ||eng d
020 ▼a 9781392512562
035 ▼a (MiAaPQ)AAI22585101
040 ▼a MiAaPQ ▼c MiAaPQ ▼d 247004
0820 ▼a 100
1001 ▼a Rudolph, Rachel E.
24510 ▼a Talking about Appearances: Experience, Evaluation, and Evidence in Discourse.
260 ▼a [S.l.]: ▼b University of California, Berkeley., ▼c 2019.
260 1 ▼a Ann Arbor: ▼b ProQuest Dissertations & Theses, ▼c 2019.
300 ▼a 145 p.
500 ▼a Source: Dissertations Abstracts International, Volume: 81-06, Section: A.
500 ▼a Advisor: MacFarlane, John
5021 ▼a Thesis (Ph.D.)--University of California, Berkeley, 2019.
506 ▼a This item must not be sold to any third party vendors.
520 ▼a When we say that a dress looks blue, or that a musical instrument sounds off-key, or that a soup smells like it contains nutmeg, what do we communicate? With claims about appearances like these we seem to communicate both about the objective world and about our subjective experience. This comes out in two puzzling features of appearance claims.Faultless disagreement arises when speakers disagree, and yet neither seems to be mistaken. Speakers may faultlessly disagree about appearances, for instance if one holds that a dress 'looks blue', and the other that it doesn't. There is a felt incompatibility here, just as with disagreement over objective claims. But assuming the speakers have different visual experiences of the dress, neither seems to be mistaken. Which appearance claim a speaker correctly makes depends not just on the objective world, but on their subjective experience as well. Faultless disagreement thus precludes viewing appearance claims as straightforwardly objective or subjective.The acquaintance inference is the inference from an utterance to the conclusion that the speaker has relevant first-hand acquaintance. For instance, if a speaker says that the dress looks blue, one will infer that they have seen it. The utterance is infelicitous if they haven't. However, this inference is not an ordinary entailment. Just because I haven't seen the dress, doesn't mean it doesn't look blue. Again, this phenomenon precludes taking appearance claims to be straightforwardly objective or subjective.I defend an expressivist analysis of appearance claims, on which they are used to express speakers' experiential states. On this view, faultless disagreement arises when speakers express incompatible experiential states, while nonetheless expressing experiential states they are in fact in. And the acquaintance inferences arises because when a speaker makes an appearance claim, one can infer that they are in an experiential state of the sort expressed by the utterance.My analysis covers not only appearance language, but experiential language more generally, which encompasses both appearance language and the evaluative language of personal taste (e.g. 'tasty', 'interesting'). Indeed, both faultless disagreement and the acquaintance inference have been associated primarily with evaluative vocabulary. I argue, however, that these features are not especially associated with evaluative language. The language of personal taste falls in the intersection of the evaluative and the experiential
590 ▼a School code: 0028.
650 4 ▼a Philosophy.
690 ▼a 0422
71020 ▼a University of California, Berkeley. ▼b Philosophy.
7730 ▼t Dissertations Abstracts International ▼g 81-06A.
773 ▼t Dissertation Abstract International
790 ▼a 0028
791 ▼a Ph.D.
792 ▼a 2019
793 ▼a English
85640 ▼u http://www.riss.kr/pdu/ddodLink.do?id=T15492908 ▼n KERIS ▼z 이 자료의 원문은 한국교육학술정보원에서 제공합니다.
980 ▼a 202002 ▼f 2020
990 ▼a ***1008102
991 ▼a E-BOOK